René Descartes


Quick Info

Born
31 March 1596
La Haye (now Descartes),Touraine, France
Died
11 February 1650
Stockholm, Sweden

Summary
René Descartes was a French philosopher whose work, La géométrie, includes his application of algebra to geometry from which we now have Cartesian geometry. His work had a great influence on both mathematicians and philosophers.

Biography

René Descartes was a philosopher whose work, La Géométrie , includes his application of algebra to geometry from which we now have Cartesian geometry.

René Descartes' parents were Joachim Descartes (1563-1640) and Jeanne Brochard (1566-1597). Joachim, the son of the medical doctor Pierre Descartes (1515-1566), studied law and was a counsellor in the Parliament of Brittany which sat at Rennes. Jeanne was the daughter of the military man René Brochard who formed part of the garrison stationed at Poitiers. One of Jeanne's brothers, also named René Brochard, became one of René Descartes' two godfathers; René Descartes was named after his godfather René Brochard. Jeanne's widowed mother, Jeanne Sain Brochard, lived at La Haye, near Tours, and it was in her home that René was born. Joachim and Jeanne Descartes were married on 15 January 1589 and lived at Châtellerault. They had two surviving children older than René, a girl named Jeanne (born 1590) and a boy named Pierre (born 1591). René was baptised in the Roman Catholic Church of Saint George in La Haye when he was four days old. His mother died in childbirth a year after he was born and the boy, born at the time of her death, also died. At this time, René was sent back to his grandmother's home in La Haye where he was cared for by Jeanne Sain Brochard. Joachim Descartes remarried in 1600 to Anne Morin and they had a boy named Joachim (born 1602) and a girl named Anne (born 1611). René therefore had a older brother and an older sister, as well as a younger half-brother and younger half-sister. He did not return to live with his father and step-mother, however, but continued living with his grandmother at La Haye. Now René's health was poor when he was a child. Throughout his childhood, up to his twenties, he was pale and had a persistent cough which was probably due to tuberculosis. It seems likely that he inherited these health problems from his mother.

Descartes was educated at the Jesuit college of La Flèche in Anjou. He entered the college at Easter 1607 at the age of eleven years where he became a boarder. [There is some uncertainty here, with some biographers claiming that he entered the College two years earlier.] The college had opened in January 1604 so was a comparatively new school. He studied there taking courses in classics, logic and traditional Aristotelian philosophy. He also learnt mathematics from the books of Clavius, while studying all the branches of mathematics, namely arithmetic, geometry, astronomy and music. While in the school his health was poor and, instead of rising at 5 a.m. like the other boys, he was granted permission to remain in bed until 11 o'clock in the morning, a custom he maintained until the year of his death. In his final years at the school he studied natural philosophy, metaphysics and ethics. He left the La Flèche College in 1614. School had made Descartes understand how little he knew, the only subject which was satisfactory in his eyes was mathematics. This idea became the foundation for his way of thinking, and was to form the basis for all his works.

See Descartes' own words describing his schooling at THIS LINK.

Comparatively little is known of Descartes' life between 1614 and 1618. He spent a while in Paris, apparently keeping very much to himself, and some have speculated that he might have suffered some sort of a breakdown at this time. Then he studied at the University of Poitiers, receiving a law degree from Poitiers in 1616. He took the law degree to comply with his father's wishes but he quickly decided that this was not the path he wanted to follow. He wrote in Discourse on the Method:-
I entirely abandoned the study of letters, resolving to seek no knowledge other than that which could be found in myself or else in the great book of the world. I spent the rest of my youth travelling, visiting courts and armies, mixing with people of diverse temperaments and ranks, gathering various experiences, testing myself in the situations which fortune offered me, and at all times reflecting on whatever came my way so as to derive some profit from it.
He may have returned to Paris before he enlisted in the military school at Breda in 1618, becoming a volunteer in the army of Maurice of Nassau. While in Breda his formal study was of military engineering but he started studying mathematics and mechanics under the Dutch scientist Isaac Beeckman, and began to seek a unified science of nature. Advised by Beeckman, he began considering mechanical problems. While in Holland, he wrote to Beeckman in March 1619 about his new ideas:-
[I want to promote a] completely new science by which all questions in general may be solved that can be proposed about any kind of quantity, continuous as well as discrete. But each according to its own nature. ... In arithmetic, for instance, some questions can be solved by rational numbers, some by surd numbers, and others can be imagined but not solved. For continuous quantity I hope to prove that, similarly, certain problems can be solved by using only straight or circular lines, that some problems require other curves for their solution, but still curves which arise from one single motion and which therefore can be traced by the new compasses, which I consider to be no less certain and geometrical than the usual compasses by which circles are traced; and, finally, that other problems can be solved by curved lines generated by separate motions not subordinate to one another.
After this time in Holland he left the service of Maurice of Nassau and travelled through Europe with the plan to join the army of Maximilian of Bavaria. In 1619 he joined the Bavarian army and was stationed in Ulm. An important event in his life was three dreams he had in November 1619. These he believed were sent by a divine spirit with the intention of revealing to him a new approach to philosophy. The ideas from these dreams would dominate much of his work from that time on.

For Descartes' own description of the ideas that he developed at this time see THIS LINK.

While serving Maximilian of Bavaria, Descartes was present as an official observer with the Catholic League at the Battle of the White Mountain near Prague in November 1620. After this he left the army but since the plague was ravaging in Paris he could not return there but instead began a period of travel.

From 1620 to 1628 Descartes travelled through Europe, spending time in Bohemia (1620), Hungary (1621), Germany, Holland and France (1622-23). He spent time in 1623 in Paris where he made contact with Marin Mersenne, an important contact which kept him in touch with the scientific world for many years, and with Claude Mydorge. From Paris he travelled through Switzerland to Italy where he spent some time in Venice and in Rome, then he returned to France again (1625). He renewed his acquaintance with Mersenne and Mydorge, and met Girard Desargues. His Paris home became a meeting place for philosophers and mathematicians and steadily became more and more busy. By 1628 Descartes, tired of the bustle of Paris, the house full of people, and of the life of travelling he had before, decided to settle down where he could work in solitude. He gave much thought to choosing a country suited to his nature and he chose Holland. What he longed for was somewhere peaceful where he could work away from the distractions of a city such as Paris yet still have access to the facilities of a city. It was a good decision which he did not seem to regret over the next twenty years. He told Mersenne where he was living so that he might keep in touch with the mathematical world, but otherwise he kept his place of residence a secret.

Soon after he settled in Holland, Descartes began work on his first major treatise on physics, Le Monde, ou Traité de la Lumière . He wrote to Mersenne in October 1629:-
[The foundations of physics] is the topic which I have studied more than any other and in which, thank God, I have not altogether wasted my time. At least I think that I have found how to prove metaphysical truths in a manner which is more evident than the proofs of geometry - in my opinion, that is: I do not know if I shall be able to convince others of it. During my first nine months in this country I worked on nothing else.
This work was near completion when news that Galileo was condemned to house arrest reached him. He, perhaps wisely, decided not to risk publication and the work was published, only in part, after his death. He explained later his change of direction saying:-
... in order to express my judgement more freely, without being called upon to assent to, or to refute the opinions of the learned, I resolved to leave all this world to them and to speak solely of what would happen in a new world, if God were now to create ... and allow her to act in accordance with the laws He had established.
For Descartes' own description of the contents of Le Monde, ou Traité de la Lumière see THIS LINK.

In Holland, Descartes had a number of scientific friends as well as continued contact with Mersenne. His friendship with Beeckman continued and he also had contact with Mydorge, Hortensius, Huygens and Frans van Schooten (the elder). Langer [112] describes Descartes' life in Holland:-
As throughout his life he continued to do his work abed in the mornings. His evenings he generally devoted to the consideration of his correspondence, which was mainly scientific, rarely personal, and of which he was painstakingly careful, while the intermediate part of the day he gave to relaxation. In matters of money he was neither extravagant nor parsimonious, showing himself in this respect a true philosopher. He always did some entertaining, now more, now less, professing to find considerable enjoyment in conversation, though he was himself rather taciturn.
Descartes was pressed by his friends to publish his ideas and, although he was adamant in not publishing Le Monde , he wrote a treatise on science under the title Discours de la méthode pour bien conduire sa raison et chercher la vérité dans les sciences . Three appendices to this work were La Dioptrique , Les Météores , and La Géométrie . The treatise was published at Leiden in 1637 and Descartes wrote to Mersenne saying:-
I have tried in my "Dioptrique" and my "Météores" to show that my Méthode is better than the vulgar, and in my "Géométrie" to have demonstrated it.
The work describes what Descartes considers is a more satisfactory means of acquiring knowledge than that presented by Aristotle's logic. Only mathematics, Descartes feels, is certain, so all must be based on mathematics.

La Dioptrique is a work on optics and, although Descartes does not cite previous scientists for the ideas he puts forward, in fact there is little new. However his approach through experiment was an important contribution.

Les Météores is a work on meteorology and is important in being the first work which attempts to put the study of weather on a scientific basis. However many of Descartes' claims are not only wrong but could have easily been seen to be wrong if he had done some easy experiments. For example Roger Bacon had demonstrated the error in the commonly held belief that water which has been boiled freezes more quickly. However Descartes claims:-
... and we see by experience that water which has been kept on a fire for some time freezes more quickly than otherwise, the reason being that those of its parts which can be most easily folded and bent are driven off during the heating, leaving only those which are rigid.
Despite its many faults, the subject of meteorology was set on course after publication of Les Météores particularly through the work of Boyle, Hooke and Halley.

La Géométrie is by far the most important part of this work. In [22] Scott summarises the importance of this work in four points:-
  1. He makes the first step towards a theory of invariants, which at later stages derelativises the system of reference and removes arbitrariness.
  2. Algebra makes it possible to recognise the typical problems in geometry and to bring together problems which in geometrical dress would not appear to be related at all.
  3. Algebra imports into geometry the most natural principles of division and the most natural hierarchy of method.
  4. Not only can questions of solvability and geometrical possibility be decided elegantly, quickly and fully from the parallel algebra, without it they cannot be decided at all.
Some extracts from Descartes' La Géométrie are at THIS LINK.

Some ideas in La Géométrie may have come from earlier work of Oresme but in Oresme's work there is no evidence of linking algebra and geometry. Wallis in Algebra (1685) strongly argues that the ideas of La Géométrie were copied from Harriot. Wallis writes:-
... the Praxis was read by Descartes, and every line of Descartes' analysis bears token of the impression.
There seems little to justify Wallis's claim, which was probably made partly through patriotism but also through his just desires to give Harriot more credit for his work. Harriot's work on equations, however, may indeed have influenced Descartes who always claimed, clearly falsely, that nothing in his work was influenced by the work of others.

Descartes' Meditations on First Philosophy, was published in 1641, designed for the philosopher and for the theologian. It consists of six meditations, Of the Things that we may doubt, Of the Nature of the Human Mind, Of God: that He exists, Of Truth and Error, Of the Essence of Material Things, Of the Existence of Material Things and of the Real Distinction between the Mind and the Body of Man. However many scientists were opposed to Descartes' ideas including Arnauld, Hobbes and Gassendi.

The most comprehensive of Descartes' works, Principia Philosophiae was published in Amsterdam in 1644. In four parts, The Principles of Human Knowledge, The Principles of Material Things, Of the Visible World and The Earth, it attempts to put the whole universe on a mathematical foundation reducing the study to one of mechanics. This is an important point of view and was to point the way forward. Descartes did not believe in action at a distance. Therefore, given this, there could be no vacuum around the Earth otherwise there was no way that forces could be transferred. In many ways Descartes' theory, where forces work through contact, is more satisfactory than the mysterious effect of gravity acting at a distance. However Descartes' mechanics leaves much to be desired. He assumes that the universe is filled with matter which, due to some initial motion, has settled down into a system of vortices which carry the sun, the stars, the planets and comets in their paths. Despite the problems with the vortex theory it was championed in France for nearly one hundred years even after Newton showed it was impossible as a dynamical system. As Brewster, one of Newton's 19th century biographers, puts it:-
Thus entrenched as the Cartesian system was ... it was not to be wondered at that the pure and sublime doctrines of the 'Principia' were distrustfully received ... The uninstructed mind could not readily admit the idea that the great masses of the planets were suspended in empty space, and retained their orbits by an invisible influence ...
Pleasing as Descartes' theory was, even the supporters of his natural philosophy such as the Cambridge metaphysical theologian Henry More, found objections. Certainly More admired Descartes, writing:-
I should look upon Des-Cartes as a man most truly inspired in the knowledge of Nature, than any that have professed themselves so these sixteen hundred years...
However between 1648 and 1649 they exchanged a number of letters in which More made some telling objections. Descartes however in his replies makes no concessions to More's points. More went on to ask:-
Why are not your vortices in the form of columns or cylinders rather than ellipses, since any point of the axis of a vortex is as it were a centre from which the celestial matter recedes with, as far as I can see, a wholly constant impetus? ... Who causes all the planets not to revolve in one plane (the plane of the ecliptic)? ... And the Moon itself, neither in the plane of the Earth's equator nor in a plane parallel to this?
In 1644, the year his Meditations were published, Descartes visited France. He returned again in 1647, when he met Pascal and argued with him that a vacuum could not exist, and then again in 1648.

In 1649 Queen Christina of Sweden persuaded Descartes to go to Stockholm. However the Queen wanted to draw tangents at 5 a.m. and Descartes broke the habit of his lifetime of getting up at 11 o'clock. After only a few months in the cold northern climate, walking to the palace for 5 o'clock every morning, he died of pneumonia.

After his death an unfinished manuscript entitled Regulae ad directionem ingenii was found in his papers. Only the first 21 of the Rules were presented, the last three being only given by their intended titles. Sadly, the original manuscript has been lost and only copies remain. Here is a short extract from the manuscript:-
I would not value these Rules so highly if they were good only for solving those pointless problems with which arithmeticians and geometers are inclined to while away their time, for in that case all I could credit myself with achieving would be to dabble in trifles with greater subtlety than they. I shall have much to say below about figures and numbers, for no other disciplines can yield illustrations as evident and certain as these. But if one attends closely to my meaning, one will readily see that ordinary mathematics is far from my mind here, that it is quite another discipline I am expounding, and that these illustrations are more its outer garments than its inner parts. This discipline should contain the primary rudiments of human reason and extend to the discovery of truths in any field whatever. Frankly speaking, I am convinced that it is a more powerful instrument of knowledge than any other with which human beings are endowed, as it is the source of all the rest.
We should end this biography by saying a little more about Descartes as a person. In [112] Langer describes Descartes' appearance and personality:-
In appearance Descartes was a small man of rather slight figure with a large head. His nose was prominent, his lower lip somewhat protruding, his beard and moustache of a semi-military type, and his hair growing down upon his forehead almost to his eyebrows. He wore a wig of natural colour to which he always gave fastidious attention, as he did also to his clothes which were now invariably of black cloth. In demeanour he was generally cheerful, rarely gay. His manners were always refined, gentle, and polite, and his temper tranquil and easy. As a personality he was proud, somewhat aristocratically reserved, sensitive, a bit angular, and, though a shade domineering, was pre-eminently obliging.
Bertrand Russell writes [150]:-
He always was well dressed, and wore a sword. He was not industrious; he worked short hours, and read little. When he went to Holland he took few books with him, but among them were the Bible and Thomas Aquinas. His work seems to have been done with great concentration during short periods; but perhaps, to keep up the appearance of a gentlemanly amateur, he may have pretended to work less than in fact he did, for otherwise his achievements seem scarcely credible.


References (show)

  1. M S Mahoney, Biography in Dictionary of Scientific Biography (New York 1970-1990).
    See THIS LINK.
  2. Biography in Encyclopaedia Britannica.
    http://www.britannica.com/biography/Rene-Descartes
  3. W Arnold, Descartes, in H Wussing and W Arnold, Biographien bedeutender Mathematiker (Berlin, 1983).
  4. Y Belaval, Leibniz critique de Descartes (Paris, 1960).
  5. D M Clarke, Descartes' Philosophy of Science (1982).
  6. D M Clarke, Descartes: a biography (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2006).
  7. R Dugas, De Descartes à Newton par l'école anglaise (Paris, 1953).
  8. D Garber, Descartes embodied. Reading Cartesian philosophy through Cartesian science (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2001).
  9. S Gaukroger (ed.), Descartes: Philosophy, Mathematics, and Physics (1980).
  10. E S Haldane, Descartes: His Life and Times (1966).
  11. J E Hofmann, Geschichte der Mathematik. Teil I : Von den Anfängen bis zum Auftreten von Fermat und Descartes (Berlin, 1963).
  12. V Jullien, Descartes. La 'Géométrie' de 1637 (Philosophies, 76. Presses Universitaires de France, Paris, 1996).
  13. Ya Lyatker, Descartes (Spanish) (Moscow, 1990).
  14. H Montias, Descartes (French) (Paris, 1969).
  15. I Sp Papadatos, Arithmetic polygons of the ancient Greeks and arithmetic polyhedra of Descartes (Greek) (Athens, 1982).
  16. L Pearl, Descartes (1977).
  17. E Pies, Der Mordfall Descartes (Verlag E. & U. Brockhaus, Solingen, 1996).
  18. J Rée, Descartes (1974).
  19. G Rodis-Lewis (ed.), La Science chez Descartes (1987).
  20. G Rodis-Lewis, Descartes: his life and thought (Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY, 1998).
  21. C Sasaki, Descartes's mathematical thought (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 237. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, 2003).
  22. J F Scott, The Scientific Work of René Descartes (1987).
  23. M Serfati and D Descotes (eds.), Mathématiciens français du XVIIe siècle-Descartes, Fermat, Pascal (Presses Universitaires Blaise-Pascal, Clermont-Ferrand, 2008).
  24. W R Shea, The Magic of Numbers and Motion: The Scientific Career of René Descartes (1991).
  25. T Sorell, Descartes. Past Masters (New York, 1987).
  26. J R Vrooman, René Descartes: A Biography (1970).
  27. J Vuillemin, Mathématiques et métaphysique chez Descartes (Paris, 1960).
  28. O J Abdounur, Music according to Descartes, in Studies in history of mathematics dedicated to A P Youschkevitch (De Diversis Artibus, 56, Brepols, Turnhout, 2002), 173-185.
  29. O J Abdounur, The music-mathematics relation according to Descartes (Portuguese), in II Portuguese-Brazilian Conference on the History of Mathematics & II National Seminar on the History of Mathematics (Portuguese), São Paulo, 1997 (UNESP, Rio Claro, 1997), 313-322.
  30. E J Aiton, Descartes's theory of the tides, Ann. of Sci. 11 (1955), 337-348.
  31. L Alanen, On Descartes' argument for dualism and the distinction between different kinds of beings, in The logic of being (Dordrecht, 1986), 223-248.
  32. S Alarcón Vasco and C M Suescún, The method of Descartes of determining the tangent of a curve (Spanish), Mat. Enseñ. Univ. (N. S.) 19 (1) (2011), 103-114.
  33. M Araújo Silva, L'imagination dans la Géométrie de Descartes: retour sur une question ouverte, in M Serfati and D Descotes (eds.), Mathématiciens français du XVIIe siècle-Descartes, Fermat, Pascal (Presses Universitaires Blaise-Pascal, Clermont-Ferrand, 2008), 69-128.
  34. R Ariew, Descartes and Pascal, Perspect. Sci. 15 (4) (2007), 397-409.
  35. R Ariew, Descartes's fable and scientific methodology, Arch. Int. Hist. Sci. 55 (154) (2005), 127-138.
  36. R Ariew, Descartes and the Jesuits: doubt, novelty, and the Eucharist, in Jesuit science and the republic of letters (Transform. Stud. Hist. Sci. Tech., MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 2003), 157-194.
  37. O O Barabanov, Two letters from Descartes to Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia (Russian), Proceedings of the 8th International Kolmogorov Lectures (Russian) (Yaroslav. Gos. Ped. Univ. im. K. D. Ushinskogo, Yaroslavl, 2010), 404-418.
  38. E Barbin, Descartes et les mathématiques, in Les philosophes et les mathématiques (Ellipses, Paris, 1996), 43-65.
  39. M Bartolozzi and R Franci, The rule of signs, from its statement by R Descartes (1637) to its proof by C F Gauss (1828) (Italian), Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 45 (4) (1993), 335-374.
  40. A Lo Bello, Descartes and the philosophy of mathematics, The Mathematical Intelligencer 13 (1991), 35-39.
  41. J Bernhardt, La polémique de Hobbes contre la 'Dioptrique' de Descartes dans le 'Tractatus opticus II' (1644), Rev. Internat. Philos. 33 (3) (1979), 432-442.
  42. M Blay, L'organisation déductive de la science du mouvement: Descartes-Galilée-Huygens, in Philosophy on a wide scale (Italian), Tenerife, 2001 (Fund. Canar. Orotava Hist. Cienc., La Orotava, 2001), 325-336.
  43. E-J Bos, Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia and Descartes' letters (1650-1665), Historia Math. 37 (3) (2010), 485-502.
  44. E-J Bos and C Vermeulen, An unknown autograph letter of Descartes to Joachim de Wicquefort, Studia Leibnitiana 34 (1) (2002), 100-109.
  45. H J M Bos, Descartes, Pappus' problem and the Cartesian parabola : a conjecture, in The investigation of difficult things (Cambridge, 1992), 71-96.
  46. H J M Bos, On the representation of curves in Descartes' 'Géométrie', Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 24 (4) (1981), 295-338.
  47. H J M Bos, Algebraization in Descartes' 'Géométrie' (French), in Symposium dedicated to A F Monna (Utrecht, 1980), 42-57.
  48. H J M Bos, Descartes and the beginning of analytic geometry (Dutch), in Summer course 1989 : mathematics in the Golden Age (Amsterdam, 1989), 79-97.
  49. H J M Bos, La structure de la Géométrie de Descartes, in 'Pour Descartes': mathématiques et physique cartésiennes, Paris, 1996, Rev. Histoire Sci. 51 (2-3) (1998), 291-317.
  50. H J M Bos, Tradition and modernity in early modern mathematics: Viète, Descartes and Fermat, in L'Europe mathématique/Mathematical Europe (Ed. Maison des Sci. de l'Homme, Paris, 1996), 183-204.
  51. J Bouveresse, La théorie du possible chez Descartes, Rev. Internat. Philos. 37 (3) (1983), 293-318.
  52. C B Boyer, Descartes and the geometrization of algebra, Amer. Math. Monthly 66 (1959), 390-393.
  53. C B Boyer, Fermat and Descartes, Scripta Math. 18 (1952), 189-217.
  54. H Breger, Über die Hannoversche Handschrift der Descartesschen 'Regulae', Studia Leibnitiana 15 (1) (1983), 108-114.
  55. H Breger, Ein wiedergefundenes Autograph von Descartes, Studia Leibnitiana 34 (1) (2002), 110-116.
  56. J D Buchwald, Descartes's experimental journey past the prism and through the invisible world to the rainbow, Ann. of Sci. 65 (1) (2008), 1-46.
  57. H Burkhardt, Modalities in language, thought and reality in Leibniz, Descartes and Crusius, Synthese 75 (2) (1988), 183-215.
  58. A Campos, Descartes, lucky mathematical researcher (Spanish), Proceedings of the Seminar in Commemoration of the 400th Anniversary of the Birth of René Descartes (Spanish), Bogotá, 1996 (Colec. Mem., 9, Acad. Colombiana Cienc. Exact. Fís. Natur., Bogotá, 1997), 11-24.
  59. R B Carter, Descartes' methodological transformation of 'Homo sapiens' into 'Homo faber', Sudhoffs Arch. 68 (2) (1984), 225-229.
  60. J-T Chiang, The insights (curiosity) of the folium of Descartes on classical physics, Far East J. Appl. Math. 34 (2) (2009), 141-150.
  61. D M Clarke, Descartes' critique of logic, in Truth, knowledge and reality (Wiesbaden, 1981), 27-35.
  62. R L Coelho, Zur Physik von Descartes: Naturgesetze und Stossregeln, Philos. Natur. 39 (1) (2002), 45-60.
  63. P Costabel, Descartes et la mathématique de l'infini, Historia Sci. 29 (1985), 37-49.
  64. P Costabel, Descartes et la racine cubique des nombres binômes, Rev. Histoire Sci. Appl. 22 (2) (1969), 97-116.
  65. A C Crombie, Expectation, modelling and assent in the history of optics. II. Kepler and Descartes, Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 22 (1) (1991), 89-115.
  66. R De Rosa and O Bueno, Descartes on mathematical essences, ProtoSociology 25 (2008), 160-177.
  67. R Descartes, A lost theorem of Descartes (Spanish), Lect. Mat. 24 (1) (2003), 61-63.
  68. D Descotes, Aspects littéraires de la Géométrie de Descartes, Arch. Int. Hist. Sci. 55 (154) (2005), 163-191.
  69. K Devlin, Good-bye Descartes?, Math. Mag. 69 (5) (1996), 344-349.
  70. J Dhombres, La réception en France de Galilée. Les rôles différents de Peiresc et de Mersenne auprès de Gassendi, de Descartes et de Jacques Le Tenneur, in Galileo and the Galilean school in universities in the seventeenth century (Italian) (Studi Cent. Interuniv. Stor. Univ. Ital., 14, CLUEB, Bologna, 2011), 47-60.
  71. A V Dorofeeva, Descartes and his 'Geometry' (Russian), Mat. v Shkole (5) (1987), 51-53.
  72. F Duchesneau, The 'more geometrico' pattern in hypotheses from Descartes to Leibniz, in Nature mathematized I (Dordrecht-Boston, Mass., 1983), 197-214.
  73. B Eastwood, Stansfield Descartes on refraction : scientific versus rhetorical method, Isis 75 (278) (1984), 481-502.
  74. W Eisenberg, Theorienauffassungen in der Physikgeschichte. 17. Jahrhundert - zum Vergleich der Theorienauffassungen von R Descartes und C Huygens, Wiss. Z. Martin-Luther-Univ. Halle-Wittenberg Math.-Natur. Reihe 38 (1) (1989), 121-126.
  75. A Elzinga, Huygens' theory of research and Descartes' theory of knowledge. II, Z. Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 3 (1) (1972), 9-27.
  76. A Elzinga, Huygens' theory of research and Descartes' theory of knowledge. I, Z. Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 2 (2) (1971), 174-194.
  77. P J Federico, Descartes on polyhedra. A study of the 'De solidorum elementis', in Sources in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences 4 (New York-Berlin, 1982).
  78. J O Fleckenstein, Von Descartes zu Leibniz, Math.-Phys. Semesterber 11 (1964/1965), 129-143.
  79. E G Forbes, Descartes and the birth of analytic geometry, Historia Math. 4 (1977), 141-151.
  80. B Gagneux, La règle des signes de Descartes: le long cheminement d'une imprécision, in M Serfati and D Descotes (eds.), Mathématiciens français du XVIIe siècle-Descartes, Fermat, Pascal (Presses Universitaires Blaise-Pascal, Clermont-Ferrand, 2008), 129-165.
  81. M Galuzzi, Recent intepretations of Descartes' 'Géométrie' (Italian), in Science and philosophy (Milan, 1985), 643-663.
  82. M Galuzzi, The problem of tangents in Descartes' 'Géométrie' (Italian), Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 22 (1-2) (1980), 37-51.
  83. M Galuzzi, Exactness in Descartes (Italian), Lett. Mat. Pristem No. 41 (2001), 58-60.
  84. E Giusti, Le problème des tangents de Descartes à Leibniz, in 300 Jahre 'Nova methodus' von G W Leibniz (1684-1984) (Wiesbaden, 1986), 26-37.
  85. A Gloden, L'oeuvre mathématique de Descartes, 1596-1650, dans le cadre de la science de son époque et à la lumière des mathématiques modernes, Les Cahiers Luxembourgeois 27 (6) (1955), 243-250.
  86. T Gontier, Mathématiques et science universelle chez Bacon et chez Descartes, Rev. Hist. Sci. 59 (2) (2006), 285-312.
  87. G Gorham, Descartes on time and duration, Early Sci. Med. 12 (1) (2007), 28-54.
  88. J Grabiner, Descartes and problem-solving, Math. Mag. 68 (2) (1995), 83-97.
  89. M Grégoire, La correspondance entre Descartes et Fermat, in 'Pour Descartes': mathématiques et physique cartésiennes, Paris, 1996, Rev. Histoire Sci. 51 (2-3) (1998), 355-362.
  90. E Grosholz, Descartes' 'Geometry' and the classical tradition, in Revolution and continuity (Washington, DC, 1991), 183-196.
  91. E Grosholz, Descartes and Galileo : the quantification of time and force, in Mathématiques et philosophie de l'antiquité à l'âge classique (Paris, 1991), 197-215.
  92. N Guicciardini, Method versus calculus in Newton's criticisms of Descartes and Leibniz, in International Congress of Mathematicians III (Eur. Math. Soc., Zürich, 2006), 1719-1742.
  93. H-J Treder, Descartes' Physik der Hypothesen, Newtons Physik der Prinzipien und Leibnizens Physik der Prinzipe, Studia Leibnitiana 14 (2) (1982), 278-286.
  94. K Hara, Comment Descartes a-t-il découvert ses ovales?, Historia Sci. 29 (1985), 51-82.
  95. R T Harris, Mathematics, Descartes, and the rise of modernity, Philos. Math. (2) 3 (2) (1988), 1-20.
  96. K Hawlitschek, Die Deutschlandreise des René Descartes, Ber. Wiss.gesch. 25 (4) (2002), 235-252.
  97. J Henry, Metaphysics and the origins of modern science: Descartes and the importance of laws of nature, Early Sci. Med. 9 (2) (2004), 73-114.
  98. A Herreman, La fonction inaugurale de La géométrie de Descartes, Rev. Histoire Math. 18 (1) (2012), 67-156.
  99. P Hilton and J Pedersen, Descartes, Euler, Poincaré, Pólya - and polyhedra, Enseign. Math. (2) 27 (3-4) (1981), 327-343.
  100. A Hüttemann, Über das Verhältnis von Metaphysik und Physik bei Descartes, Studia Leibnitiana 28 (1) (1996), 93-107.
  101. L Indorato and P Nastasi, The 1740 resolution of the Fermat-Descartes controversy, Historia Math. 16 (2) (1989), 137-148.
  102. G Israel, The analytical method in Descartes' Géométrie, in Analysis and synthesis in mathematics (Boston Stud. Philos. Sci., 196, Kluwer Acad. Publ., Dordrecht, 1997), 3-34.
  103. A Janiak, Metaphysics and natural philosophy in Descartes and Newton, Found. Sci. 18 (3) (2013), 403-417.
  104. S A Janovskaja, On the role of mathematical rigor in the history of the creative development of mathematics and especially on the 'Geometry' of Descartes (Russian), in Studies in systems of logic (dedicated to the memory of S A Janovskaja) 'Nauka' (Moscow, 1970), 13-50.
  105. S A Janovskaja, On the role of mathematical rigor in the creative development of mathematics and especially on Descartes' 'Geometry' (Russian), Istor.-Mat. Issled. 17 (1966), 151-183.
  106. D M Jesseph, Descartes, Pascal, and the epistemology of mathematics: the case of the cycloid, Perspect. Sci. 15 (4) (2007), 410-433.
  107. A Joja, Descartes et le modèle mathémathique, An. Univ. Bucuresti Acta Logica 14 (1971), 5-27.
  108. W B Joyce and A Joyce, Descartes, Newton, and Snell's law, J. Opt. Soc. Amer. 66 (1) (1976), 1-8.
  109. V Jullien, Descartes-Roberval, une relation tumultueuse, in 'Pour Descartes': mathématiques et physique cartésiennes, Paris, 1996, Rev. Histoire Sci. 51 (2-3) (1998), 363-371.
  110. S Krämer, Uüber das Verhältnis von Algebra und Geometrie in Descartes' 'Géométrie', Philos. Natur. 26 (1) (1989), 19-40.
  111. A A Krishnaswami Ayyangar, Rene Descartes, Math. Student 8 (1940), 101-108.
  112. R E Langer, René Descartes, Amer. Math. Monthly 44 (8) (1937), 495-512.
  113. M Laserna, Analytic geometry, experimental truth and metaphysics in Descartes, in Proceedings of the Seminar in Commemoration of the 400th Anniversary of the Birth of René Descartes (Spanish), Bogotá, 1996 (Colec. Mem., 9, Acad. Colombiana Cienc. Exact. Fís. Natur., Bogotá, 1997), 51-92.
  114. T M Lennon, The Leibnizean picture of Descartes, in Nature mathematized I (Dordrecht-Boston, Mass., 1983), 215-226.
  115. T Lenoir, Descartes and the geometrization of thought : the methodological background of Descartes' 'Géométrie', Historia Math. 6 (4) (1979), 355-379.
  116. R J Levene, Sources of confusion in Descartes's illustrations, with reference to the history of contact lenses, in History of science 6 (Cambridge, 1967), 90-96.
  117. F Le Lionnais, Descartes et Einstein, Rev. Hist. Sci. Appl. 5 (1952), 139-154.
  118. G Loeck, Descartes' logic of magnitudes, Dialectica 43 (4) (1989), 339-372.
  119. M Di Loreto, The 'Stockholm inventory' and 'First register' of Descartes : Marginal notes on the posthumous mathematical works (Italian), Nuncius Ann. Storia Sci. 10 (2) (1995), 551-615.
  120. J Lützen, The algebra of geometric impossibility: Descartes and Montucla on the impossibility of the duplication of the cube and the trisection of the angle, Centaurus 52 (1) (2010), 4-37.
  121. A Malet, Gregorie, Descartes, Kepler, and the law of refraction, Arch. Internat. Hist. Sci. 40 (125) (1990), 278-304.
  122. P Mancosu, Descartes's 'Géométrie' and revolutions in mathematics, in Revolutions in mathematics (New York, 1992), 83-116.
  123. P Mancosu and A Arana, Descartes and the cylindrical helix, Historia Math. 37 (3) (2010), 403-427.
  124. K Manders, Algebra in Roth, Faulhaber, and Descartes, Historia Math. 33 (2) (2006), 184-209.
  125. S Maronne, Pascal versus Descartes on solution of geometrical problems and the Sluse-Pascal correspondence, Early Sci. Med. 15 (4-5) (2010), 537-565.
  126. S Maronne, The ovals of the Excerpta mathematica and the origins of Descartes' method of normals, Historia Math. 37 (3) (2010), 460-484.
  127. S Maronne, Sur une lettre de Descartes à Schooten qu'on dit de 1639, Correspondence: Descartes, René-van Schooten, Frans, Rev. Histoire Math. 12 (2) (2006), 199-248
  128. M Martinet, Science et hypothèses chez Descartes, Arch. Internat. Hist. Sci. 24 (95) (1974), 319-339.
  129. D R Mazhary, Contraintes socio-culturelles et conversions philosophiques chez Descartes. Casualité vs. causalité, in Proceedings of the Seminar in Commemoration of the 400th Anniversary of the Birth of René Descartes (Spanish), Bogotá, 1996 (Colec. Mem., 9, Acad. Colombiana Cienc. Exact. Fís. Natur., Bogotá, 1997), 111-133.
  130. J E McGuire, Space, geometrical objects and infinity : Newton and Descartes on extension, in Nature mathematized I (Dordrecht-Boston, Mass., 1983), 69-112.
  131. R Meyer, René Descartes. Betrachtungen zum Verhältnis von Philosophie und Naturwissenschaften im 17. Jahrhundert, in Naturwissenschaftliche Revolution im 17. Jahrhundert (Berlin, 1989), 55-63.
  132. A G Molland, Shifting the foundations : Descartes's transformation of ancient geometry, Historia Math. 3 (1976), 21-49.
  133. R H Moorman, The influence of mathematics on the philosophy of Descartes, Nat. Math. Mag. 17 (1943), 296-307.
  134. C Müller, Descartes' 'Géométrie' und die Begründung der höheren Analysis, Sudhoffs Arch. 40 (1956), 240-258.
  135. A Nardi, Descartes 'presque' galiléen : 18 février 1643, Rev. Histoire Sci. 39 (1) (1986), 3-16.
  136. D V Nikulin, The argument over the nature of extent : Henry More and René Descartes (Russian), Voprosy Istor. Estestvoznan. i Tekhn. (4) (1989), 3-11.
  137. L Nolan, Descartes' theory of universals, Philos. Stud. 89 (2-3) (1998), 161-180.
  138. G Nonnoi, Against emptiness : Descartes's physics and metaphysics of plenitude, Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 25 (1) (1994), 81-96.
  139. M Paty, Mathesis universalis and intelligibility in Descartes (Portuguese), Cad. Hist. Filos. Ciênc. (3) 8 (1) (1998), 9-57.
  140. M Paty, Mathesis universalis and intelligibility in Descartes (Spanish), in Proceedings of the Seminar in Commemoration of the 400th Anniversary of the Birth of René Descartes (Spanish), Bogotá, 1996 (Colec. Mem., 9, Acad. Colombiana Cienc. Exact. Fís. Natur., Bogotá, 1997), 135-170.
  141. J Pla i Carrera, Archimedes and Descartes: method with a change of language (Catalan), Butl. Soc. Catalana Mat. 13 (2) (1998), 35-84.
  142. D Rabouin, What Descartes knew of mathematics in 1628, Historia Math. 37 (3) (2010), 428-459.
  143. R Rashed, Descartes et l'infiniment petit, Boll. Stor. Sci. Mat. 33 (1) (2013), 151-169.
  144. R Rashed, De la dioptrique à la géométrie: les ovales de Descartes, Physis Riv. Internaz. Storia Sci. (N.S.) 42 (2) (2005), 333-354.
  145. R Rashed, La modernité mathématique: Descartes et Fermat, in Philosophie des mathématiques et théorie de la connaissance (Collect. Sci. Hist., Lib. Sci. Tech. Albert Blanchard, Paris, 2005), 239-252.
  146. G Restrepo Sierra, Descartes and modern science (Spanish), Lect. Mat. 13 (1-3) (1992), 25-51.
  147. G Restrepo Sierra, René Descartes: a belief in scientism? (Spanish), in Proceedings of the Seminar in Commemoration of the 400th Anniversary of the Birth of René Descartes (Spanish), Bogotá, 1996 (Colec. Mem., 9, Acad. Colombiana Cienc. Exact. Fís. Natur., Bogotá, 1997), 171-206.
  148. G Rodis-Lewis, Quelques remarques sur la question de la vitesse de la lumière chez Descartes, in 'Pour Descartes': mathématiques et physique cartésiennes, Paris, 1996, Rev. Histoire Sci. 51 (2-3) (1998), 347-354.
  149. G A J Rogers, Descartes and the method of English science, Ann. of Sci. 29 (1972), 237-255.
  150. B Russell, Descartes, in History of Western Philosophy (George Allen & Unwin Ltd., London, 1961), 542-551.
  151. S Sakellariadis, Descartes' experimental proof of the infinite velocity of light and Huygens' rejoinder, Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 26 (1) (1982), 1-12.
  152. S Sakellariadis, Descartes's use of empirical data to test hypotheses, Isis 73 (266) (1982), 68-76.
  153. H Samelson, Descartes and differential geometry, in Geometry, topology, and physics (Conf. Proc. Lecture Notes Geom. Topology, IV, Int. Press, Cambridge, MA, 1995), 323-328.
  154. A Saxon Dean, An investigation of pedagogical techniques in Descartes' La géométrie, British Society for History of Mathematics Bull. 26 (3) (2011), 167-177.
  155. I Schneider, Die Rolle des Formalen und des Individuums in der Mathematik bei Descartes und Leibniz, Sudhoffs Arch. 58 (1974), 225-234.
  156. I Schneider, Trends in German mathematics at the time of Descartes' stay in southern Germany, in M Serfati and D Descotes (eds.), Mathématiciens français du XVIIe siècle-Descartes, Fermat, Pascal (Presses Universitaires Blaise-Pascal, Clermont-Ferrand, 2008), 45-67.
  157. I Schneider, Wie Huren und Betrüger-die Begegnung des jungen Descartes mit der Welt der Praktiker der Mathematik, Ber. Wiss.gesch. 20 (2-3) (1997), 173-188.
  158. J A Schuster, Physico-mathematics and the search for causes in Descartes' optics-1619-1637, Synthese 185 (3) (2012), 467-499.
  159. M Serfati, Constructivismes et obscurités dans la Géométrie de Descartes. Quelques remarques philosophiques, in M Serfati and D Descotes (eds.), Mathématiciens français du XVIIe siècle-Descartes, Fermat, Pascal (Presses Universitaires Blaise-Pascal, Clermont-Ferrand, 2008), 11-44.
  160. M Serfati, A note on the Geometry and Descartes's mathematical work, Notices Amer. Math. Soc. 55 (1) (2008), 50-53.
  161. M Serfati, Le développement de la pensée mathématique du jeune Descartes (l'éveil d'un mathématicien), in De la méthode (Colloq. Sémin., Press. Univ. Franc-Comtoises, Besançon, 2002), 39-104.
  162. M Serfati, Descartes et la constitution de l'écriture symbolique mathématique, in 'Pour Descartes': mathématiques et physique cartésiennes, Paris, 1996, Rev. Histoire Sci. 51 (2-3) (1998), 237-289.
  163. M Serfati, Introduction. 'Pour Descartes': mathématiques et physique cartésiennes, in 'Pour Descartes': mathématiques et physique cartésiennes, Paris, 1996, Rev. Histoire Sci. 51 (2-3) (1998), 171-182.
  164. A E Shapiro, Light, pressure, and rectilinear propagation : Descartes' celestial optics and Newton's hydrostatics, Studies in Hist. and Philos. Sci. 5 (1974), 239-296.
  165. W R Shea, Descartes : methodological ideal and actual procedure, Philos. Natur. 21 (2-4) (1984), 577-589.
  166. W R Shea, The 'rational' Descartes and the 'empirical' Galileo, in The reception of the Galilean science of motion in seventeenth-century Europe (Boston Stud. Philos. Sci., 239, Kluwer Acad. Publ., Dordrecht, 2004), 67-82.
  167. P Slezak, Descartes's diagonal deduction, British J. Philos. Sci. 34 (1) (1983), 13-36.
  168. E Slowik, Descartes, spacetime, and relational motion, Philos. Sci. 66 (1) (1999), 117-139.
  169. J Stedall, John Wallis and the French: his quarrels with Fermat, Pascal, Dulaurens, and Descartes, Historia Math. 39 (3) (2012), 265-279.
  170. R C Taliaferro, The concept of matter in Descartes and Leibniz, Notre Dame Mathematical Lectures 9 (Notre Dame, Ind., 1964).
  171. M Tarina, La géométrie de Descartes en perspective historique, in The XVIIIth National Conference on Geometry and Topology (Cluj-Napoca, 1988), 207-208.
  172. D Tiemersma, Methodological and theoretical aspects of Descartes' treatise on the rainbow, Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 19 (3) (1988), 347-364.
  173. B Timmermans, The originality of Descartes's conception of analysis as discovery, J. Hist. Ideas 60 (3) (1999), 433-447.
  174. S Q Tong, Descartes' way of thinking about mathematics (Chinese), Qufu Shifan Daxue Xuebao Ziran Kexue Ban 20 (1) (1994), 89-95.
  175. R Torres Hernández, Descartes and quadratic equations (Spanish), Cubo Mat. Educ. 4 (1) (2002), 65-74.
  176. C van Randenborgh, Frans van Schootens Beitrag zu Descartes Discours de la méthode, Math. Semesterber. 59 (2) (2012), 223-241.
  177. J A van Ruler, Descartes' theory of vortices (Dutch), in Summer course 1996 : chaos (CWI Syllabi, 41, Math. Centrum, Centrum Wisk. Inform., Amsterdam, 1996), 9-17.
  178. L Vekerdi, Descartes' method for drawing a tangent (Hungarian), Mat. Lapok 17 (1966), 165-179.
  179. L Vekerdi, The infinitesimal method of Descartes for computing the area of the cycloid (Hungarian), Mat. Lapok 15 (1964), 196-203.
  180. C Vilain, Descartes, correspondant scientifique de Constantyn Huygens, in 'Pour Descartes': mathématiques et physique cartésiennes, Paris, 1996, Rev. Histoire Sci. 51 (2-3) (1998), 373-379.
  181. S A Voho, Ordre et mathématiques chez Descartes, in Mathématiques- philosophie et enseignement (Yamoussoukro, 1994), 55-59.
  182. B Wardhaugh, Musical logarithms in the seventeenth century: Descartes, Mercator, Newton, Historia Math. 35 (1) (2008), 19-36.
  183. P Weingartner, The ideal of the mathematization of all sciences and of 'more geometrico' in Descartes and Leibniz, in Nature mathematized I (Dordrecht-Boston, Mass., 1983), 151-195.
  184. K Weinrich, Die Lichtbrechung in den Theorien von Descartes und Fermat, Sudhoffs Arch. 1998 (suppl. 40) (1998), 1-171.

Additional Resources (show)


Honours (show)


Cross-references (show)

  1. History Topics: A history of Topology
  2. History Topics: A history of set theory
  3. History Topics: A history of the calculus
  4. History Topics: A history of time: Classical time
  5. History Topics: Abstract linear spaces
  6. History Topics: An overview of the history of mathematics
  7. History Topics: Light through the ages: Ancient Greece to Maxwell
  8. History Topics: Mathematics and art - perspective
  9. History Topics: Matrices and determinants
  10. History Topics: Perfect numbers
  11. History Topics: Quadratic, cubic and quartic equations
  12. History Topics: Science in the 17th century: From Europe to St Andrews
  13. History Topics: The function concept
  14. History Topics: The fundamental theorem of algebra
  15. History Topics: The mathematician and the forger
  16. History Topics: Theories of gravitation
  17. Famous Curves: Cartesian Oval
  18. Famous Curves: Cycloid
  19. Famous Curves: Equiangular Spiral
  20. Famous Curves: Folium of Descartes
  21. Famous Curves: Hyperbolic Spiral
  22. Famous Curves: Trident of Newton
  23. Societies: Catalan Mathematical Society
  24. Societies: Paris Academy of Sciences
  25. Student Projects: D'Arcy Thompson and Mathematics: Chapter 3
  26. Other: 10th November
  27. Other: 15th February
  28. Other: 1908 ICM - Rome
  29. Other: 1924 ICM - Toronto
  30. Other: 2009 Most popular biographies
  31. Other: 23rd August
  32. Other: 6th April
  33. Other: 8th June
  34. Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (A)
  35. Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (C)
  36. Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (D)
  37. Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (E)
  38. Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (I)
  39. Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (L)
  40. Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (O)
  41. Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (R)
  42. Other: Earliest Uses of Symbols for Variables
  43. Other: Earliest Uses of Symbols from Geometry
  44. Other: Earliest Uses of Symbols of Operation
  45. Other: Jeff Miller's postage stamps
  46. Other: London Learned Societies
  47. Other: Most popular biographies – 2024
  48. Other: Popular biographies 2018
  49. Other: The Dynamics of the Solar System

Written by J J O'Connor and E F Robertson
Last Update November 2014